<< Chapter < Page | Chapter >> Page > |
We introduce next into the set of real numbers some geometric concepts, namely, a notion of distance between numbers.Of course this had to happen, for geometry is the very basis of mathematics.
The absolute value of a real number is denoted by and is defined as follows:
We define the distance between two real numbers and by
Obviously, such definitions of absolute value and distance can be made in any ordered field.
Let and be real numbers.
Let and be real numbers for which By the open interval (a,b) we mean the set of all real numbers for which and by the closed interval [a,b] we mean the set of all real numbers for which
By we mean the set of all real numbers for which and by we mean the set of all real numbers for which
Analogously, we define and to be respectively the set of all real numbers for which and the set of all real numbers for which
Here is one of those assertions that seems like an obvious fact. However, it requires a proof which we only now can give, for it depends on the completeness axiom,and in fact is false in some ordered fields.
Let denote the set of natural Numbers, thought of as a subset of . Then is not bounded above.
Suppose false. Let be an upper bound for the nonempty set and let be the least upper bound for Taking to be the positive number 1/2, and applying Theorem 1.5, we have that there exists an element of such that But then or, So But because is an upper bound for We have thus arrived at a contradiction, and the theorem is proved.
REMARK As mentioned above, there do exist ordered fields in which the subset is bounded above. Such fields give rise to what is called “nonstandard analysis,”and they were first introduced by Abraham Robinson in 1966. The fact that is a complete ordered field is apparently crucial to be able to conclude the intuitively clear fact thatthe natural numbers have no upper bound.
[link] presents another intuitively obvious fact, and this one is in some real sense the basis for many of our upcoming arguments about limits.It relies on the preceding theorem, is in fact just a corollary, so it has to be considered as a rather deep property of the real numbers; it is not something that works in every ordered field.
Prove that if is a positive real number, then there exists a natural number such that
[link] and [link] show that the set of rational numbers is “everywhere dense” in the field That is, every real number can be approximated arbitrarily closely by rational numbers.Again, we point out that this result holds in any complete ordered field, and it is the completeness that is critical.
Let be two real numbers. Then there exists a rational number in the open interval In fact, there exist infinitely many rational numbers in the interval
If and then taking satisfies the first statement of the theorem. Assume first that and Let be a natural number for which is less than the positive number (Here, we are using the completeness of the field, because we are referring to Theorem 1.7, where completeness was vital.)If then Setting we would have that So, again, the first part of the theorem would be proved in that case.
Suppose then that and choose the natural number to be such that is less than the minimum of the two positive numbers and Now, because the number is not an upper bound for the set we may let be the smallest natural number that is larger than Set
We have first that implying that Also, because is the smallest natural number larger than we must have that Therefore, or implying that Hence, and and the first statement of the theorem is provedwhen both and are nonnegative.
If both and are nonpositive, then both and are nonnegative, and, using the first part of the proof, we can find a rational number such that So, and the first part of the theorem is proved in this case as well.
Clearly, we may replace by and repeat the argument to obtain another rational such that Then, replacing by and repeating the argument, we get a third rational such that Continuing this procedure would lead to an infinite number of rationals, all between and This proves the second statement of the theorem.
The preceding exercise shows the “denseness” of the rationals and the irrationals in the reals. It is essentially clear from this that every real number is arbitrarily close to a rational number and an irrational one.
Notification Switch
Would you like to follow the 'Analysis of functions of a single variable' conversation and receive update notifications?